Skip to main content

Betting Strategies

What follows is a short introduction to the basic strategies when dealing with prediction markets. It is by no means a complete guide.

Recall that the asset prices in prediction markets are used to form a prediction of future events, and the right AMMs are proper in the sense that they incentivize the traders (which are in this context often referred to as informants) to change the prices so that they reflect their beliefs.

Before you become an informant and expose yourself to a prediction market, you need a belief. This belief could be anything from "AA is definitely going to occur" or "AA is not going to occur with a probability of 80%" to "The following probability distribution is correct", etc.

The first example is a bit curious because it is seldom reasonable to assume that something will happen almost certainly. In prediction markets, you usually don't bet that one particular thing is going to happen, you bet on the probability of each of the possible outcomes of an event. This is a common misconception regarding prediction markets: They don't predict that an event will definitely have a particular outcome, but instead predict a probability distribution for the possible outcomes.

For example, you might believe that a particular team will definitely win their next game. But maybe the probability of that happening is only 80%. This means that buying the corresponding token isn't always a winning move (more details below). Just like in Poker, where going all-in with the stronger hand isn't necessarily a good move and doesn't guarantee a win, buying the tokens of the most likely event isn't always a good idea.

In fact, no matter how good your prediction is, you cannot guarantee a profit. For example, if you buy a number of tokens for an outcome AA that you believe to be 90% certain at the price of 50 cent, that's a good deal (assuming you are correct): There's a 90% chance that you will double your money. But according to your own beliefs, there's also a 10% chance that your stake will go up in flames. Swings like these aren't uncommon in prediction markets.

So, just like in Poker, instead of trying to win every game, we try to trade profitably over time by maximizing our expected value, which is defined as the probability-weighted average over all possible outcomes. For example, in the example above, the expected value is

p(A)$1+p(¬A)$0$0.5=$0.4p(A) \cdot \$1 + p(\neg A) \cdot \$0 - \$0.5 = \$0.4

(assuming that our beliefs are correct, the probability of AA is 0.90.9 and the probability of "not AA" is p(¬A)=0.1p(\neg A) = 0.1; if AA doesn't occur, then we lose our stake). Still a good deal (expected profit of 80%), but definitely not risk-free (10% chance of total loss).

осторожно

Prediction markets are high-risk high-reward games. Optimizing your expected results does not protect you from massive downswings.

Note that all our projections about profit are based on the assumption that our beliefs are correct (if we didn't assume that, we should probably not betting on our beliefs in the first place.). If your prediction is incorrect, you're unlikely to profit.

Of course, we may never know if any prediction was correct. For example, if you believe that the probabilities of AA and BB are 90% and 10%, resp. and then BB occurs - well, that doesn't mean you were wrong. Your prediction may have been spot-on and it just so happened that things played out in an unusual way.

Below are some general notes on how to optimize the standard interactions with categorical and scalar markets, especially with regard to providing liquidity. The last section is a TL;DR.

примечание

You can short a token (bet that the event will not occur) by buying the same amount of all other tokens. With Zeitgeist's current market maker, this can be implemented by first buying xx full sets and then selling xx units of the token you wish to short on the market. In fact, you can create all sorts of compound bets by buying full sets and then selling only certain tokens to the market maker.

Trading Categorical Markets

Suppose there's a categorical market and you believe that a particular outcome AA has a probability of p(A)p(A). Let qq be the price of the outcome. Then the expected profit of buying one AA token

p(A)$1qp(A) \cdot \$1 - q

(you pay qq, and if AA occurs, then you receive one dollar; otherwise you go broke).

This leads to a very simple strategy: If the price of AA is lower than your prediction, buy AA. That way, you're betting that AA is more likely to occur than predicted by the market. If, on the other hand, the price of AA is higher than your prediction you short AA, either by selling AA (if you own any) or by buying the same amount of all other outcome tokens. This means you're betting that AA is less likely to occur than currently predicted by the market. In particular, it is absolutely a valid strategy to own multiple outcome tokens in a market.

The farther off the price is from your prediction, the higher the profit. Note that, as discussed above, we're assuming that your prediction is correct. The more your prediction diverges from the actual probabilities, the higher the risk of making a loss.

Trading Scalar Markets

Suppose there's a scalar market with a range of [a,b][a, b]. Let pp and qq be the spot prices of SHORT and LONG, resp. Recall that p+q=1p + q = 1. The value predicted by the market is v=pa+qbv = pa + qb. Assume you believe that the market will resolve to w[a,b]w \in [a, b]. Given the current status p,q,vp, q, v of the market, how should you bet?

The SHORT token takes on more value as the value that the market resolves to is closer to the lower bound aa, and LONG tokens on more value as the value that the market resolves to is closer to the upper bound bb. In fact, suppose that your belief is correct and the market resolves to ww. Then each LONG is worth (wa)/(ba)(w - a) / (b - a) and each SHORT is worth (bw)/(ba)(b - w) / (b - a).

Thus, if the market resolves to ww, then the profit of buying one unit of LONG at the price of qq and later redeeming it is

wabaq=wvba\frac{w - a}{b - a} - q = \frac{w - v}{b - a}

(using v=pa+qb=a+q(ba)v = pa + qb = a + q(b - a); a negative profit means a loss, of course). Thus, the trade is good whenever w>vw > v. In other words, a reasonable informant buys LONG if they believe the prediction is too low. Note that the result of this buy is that the price of LONG increases, as does the value predicted by the scalar market, reflecting that the informant has provided information to the market. Since buying LONG is equivalent to selling/shorting SHORT, if you already own SHORT tokens, you can sell SHORT tokens in this situation instead of buying more LONG tokens.

Similarly, the profit of buying one unit of SHORT at the price of pp is (vw)/(ba)(v - w) / (b - a), so a reasonable informant buys SHORT if they believe the prediction is too high.

If ww lies outside of the scalar range [a,b][a, b], then just assume that w=aw = a if w<aw < a or w=bw = b if w>bw > b and apply the system above.

Providing Liquidity

Trades on prediction markets shift the price of the assets. Buying (resp. selling) an outcome asset increases (resp. decreases) its price and decreases (resp. increases) the prices of the other outcome assets. By buying (resp. selling) you bet that the probability of the outcome is higher (resp. lower) than currently predicted by the market. But how can you expose yourself to the market if you think that the prices are correct? This is where providing liquidity comes into play.

The liquidity of a market is important for creating accurate predictions. When a trader buys tokens, they are giving up information in exchange for a potential pay-off (if they are correct, they make a profit). The more significant the price movement, the more information they are providing. But if prices slip too quickly due to a lack of liquidity, their profits are comparatively small to the value of their information.

Thus, informants and liquidity providers are taking opposite sides of a bet. When liquidity providers sell to the informants, they are hoping that the assets are overpriced relative to their likelihood, while the traders assume that the asset is underpriced. But when informants buy, the prices go up, which means, provided the LPs are correct, that they are overpaying, resulting in a profit for the LPs. The same applies to selling.

As an extreme example, imagine the informants are buying out a token which the LPs know to be incorrect, even at prices close to 1$. The LPs receive fees and keep the profits made from selling the incorrect outcome tokens, which will be worthless after the market has resolved. But they also kept the correct outcome tokens (their initial investment), giving them a considerable profit. Conversely, if there's an information shock and the informants are able to conclude which outcome the market will resolve to, they will buy all of these tokens from the pool and leave the LPs holding bags of incorrect (this is, worthless) outcome tokens.

In particular, providing liquidity is just as risky as trading on a market. In case of an information shock, you stand to lose your entire position (for example, if the outcome of the event is revealed before the market closes). When the LPs take a loss to the informants, this may be explained by thinking of the liquidity providers' losses as payment for the informants' services.

Increasing the liquidity of a pool by adding tokens does not change any of the prices, but it has the effect of making it harder for traders to move the prices. This is sometimes described by saying that the market's thickness is increased. As a result, traders as able to take greater risks by opening larger positions, incentivizing them more to give up what they know about future events. But from the LPs perspective, this is also a good thing, as it gives the informants more rope. Thus, providing liquidity can be thought of increasing your position in your bet against the market.

So, users should provide liquidity when the spot prices are at the level that they should be at according to their prediction. The traders then pay money to receive outcome tokens and shift the prediction to what they believe to be the correct probability distribution. If they get it right, the liquidity provider will incur a loss. But if the LPs initial prediction is correct, then their expected profit is non-negative (this isn't straightforward to prove); but the farther the informants' probability distribution diverges from the LPs prediction and the more market noise that occurs while the price moves from the initial to the final prediction, the higher the LPs expected profit. Even if the final prediction is equal to the initial prediction, the LPs will still have collected fees. In particular, when you create a pool, you should always set the initial prices according to the probabilities that you predict.

By withdrawing some of their liquidity, on the other hand, an LP removes funds from their bet against the market. They might do this to take profits (including swap fees) or because they have lost faith in their prediction.

Minimizing Losses When Gathering Information

Roughly speaking, there are two motivations for creating a market or providing liquidity. One is to create a market that allows you to bet against the informants that are active on Zeitgeist, as discussed above. This can be profitable if the liquidity providers have information which gives them an advantage over the traders.

The other motivation is to gather information from the traders. This is the exact reversal of the situation above. The liquidity providers start off with as good a prediction they can muster (based on whatever they know about the topic), which is then corrected by the informants. If the market eventually yields a better prediction, this results in a loss for the liquidity providers, but they receive a better prediction as compensation.

The question then is how the liquidity providers can minimize losses or maximize the quality of information they receive. The liquidity is key. If the pool is too shallow, and, thus, the market is too thin, then the potential losses for the LPs are quite small, and it is very easy for traders to move the price. But this is not a good situation for the traders: Not only do they deal with excessive slippage, but they are also forced to give up their information at a very low price. For example, if the pool is so shallow that any trader can only buy 10 units of a particular outcome token, their profit is limited to $10. Most non-publicly available information is worth more than that, and may very well discourage knowledgeable informants from participating in the market, which may hurt the quality of the prediction.

On the other hand, if the pool is too deep, and, thus, the market is too thick, then the potential losses of the LPs is quite large, and it is very difficult for the traders to move the price. This is good for the traders, though, as they can buy tokens and lower prices. And just as thin markets can have a negative effect on the prediction, so can markets that are too thick. While a particularly thick market may incentivize a knowledgeable whale to join the market and give up some crucial bit of information in exchange for the chance of a particularly big payoff, it can also make it too hard for traders to move the price, which may again hurt the quality of the prediction.

In summary, the liquidity providers control both their risk and the quality of the prediction by adding or withdrawing liquidity. Thin markets can result in a lack of participation, while thick markets can lead to significant losses and slow price changes. Manually adjusting the liquidity according to market signals is often necessary.

Summary

  • For categorical markets: If you estimate that the probability of a categorical outcome is pp, then buy the corresponding token if its price is smaller than pp and short the token if its price is larger than pp.
  • For scalar markets: If you estimate that the result of a scalar market will be ww, then buy LONG if the current estimate is smaller than ww and buy SHORT if the current estimate is larger than ww.
  • Provide liquidity if you believe the current prices are correct. This is a bet against the other informants
  • Withdraw liquidity to take profits or if you believe that a justified market correction is about to happen.